home | index | units | counting | geometry | algebra | trigonometry & functions | calculus
analysis | sets & logic | number theory | recreational | misc | nomenclature & history | physics

Final Answers
© 2000-2016   Gérard P. Michon, Ph.D.

Mathematical Proofs

What's asserted without proof
can be denied without proof
.
Euclid of Megara  (c.450-374 BC)
 
An example is no proof.
Yiddish proverb.
 
The interest I have to believe a thing
is no proof that such a thing exists
.
François-Marie Arouet, known as  Voltaire  (1691-1778)
 
Absence of proof is not proof of absence.
Attributed to William Cowper (1731-1800)
 
When you've eliminated the impossible, whatever
remains, however improbable, must be the truth
.
Sherlock Holmes, in  "The Sign of the Four"  (1890)
by  Sir Arthur Conan Doyle  (1859-1930)
 
Mathematical works do consist of proofs,
just as poems do consist of characters
.
Vladimir Arnold  (1937-2010)

Contents of this Page :

 border
 border
 border

Related articles:


Related Links (Outside this Site)

Proof Wiki
Proofs in Mathematics  by  Alexander Bogomolny.
Fermat's Last Theorem for Cubes  by  Kevin S. Brown.
Theorem of the Day  (related sites)  by  Robin Whitty.
The Hundred Greatest Theorems  (of Paul and Jack Abad )  by  Nathan W. Kahl.

Video :   Proof theory foundations (2013) by  Franck Pfenning   [ 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 ]

 
border
border

What's a  Proof ?


(2007-01-09)   Only "negatives" are worth proving.
"You can't prove a negative"  is a proverb about  tests,  not proofs.

To a mathematician, "proofs" are not restricted to mere "tests".  Arguably, in the above adage, the very word "negative" lacks clear meaning as well  (since most statements could be cast in either "positive" or "negative" forms).  To play along, we should dub the first of the following sentences "positive" and the second one "negative":

  • A square  can  be the sum of two nonzero squares.
  • A cube  cannot  be the sum of two nonzero cubes.

Both statements are true in the realm of integers.  The first one can be "proved" by just one example  (the most popular of many is 25 = 16+9).  On the other hand, the second statement tells that counterexamples do not exist...  That affirmation can only be supported by a piece of reasoning, since a lack of solutions can never be demonstrated by many failed attempts.

To the author of the above infamous proverb, such a thing was clearly inconceivable.  Yet, it's precisely what mathematicians call a  proof.  Once you've seen and understood just one such proof, you'll know better.

A proof that a cube can't be the sum of two cubes can be given using the  method of infinite descent.  An example of that method is a clever 2-line proof  (which repays study)  that  there's no rational whose square is  2 :

Since 1 < Ö2 < 2,  if a positive integer  n  was making  nÖ2  an integer, the  smaller positive integer  m = (Ö2-1) n  would make  mÖ2  an integer also!  QED

Another proof  invokes the concept of divisibility.  It may be easier and more intuitive, but it's less  elementary  (it relies on more  previous  knowledge).


(2012-06-11)   Proof by induction.
The basic way to prove a statement about infinitely many things.

The elementary type of induction  (as taught at the high-school level)  pertains to integers:  To establish that some statement  P(n)  is true for all nonnegative integers, you only have to show that:

  • P(0)  is true.
  • Assuming the truth of  P(i)  for every  i < n  (the so-called  induction hypothesis)  it can be proved that  P(n)  is true.
Although the first part is pleonastic  (it's only a special case of the second part with  n=0, with a vacuous induction hypothesis)  it's useful to keep it, since the proof of the second part would otherwise almost always start with a distinction between  n=0  and the other cases.

That type of elementary induction could be reformulated to apply to the elements of any  countable  set.

However, the general concept of induction  (sometimes known as  structural induction )  has no such restrictions.  Loosely stated:

If something is true of the simplest things and can be shown to hold true of more complex things by assuming it's true of simpler ones, then it holds true of the most complex things.

In this context, it's just assumed that those "most complex things" are structually composed of simpler ones in a predefined way.  For example, Conway's surreal numbers are simply built from simpler surreal numbers.  Structural induction can thus be used to establish the validity of a statement about all surreal numbers  (there are uncountably many of them)  in a way that does not reduce to simple induction on integers.

The Peano axioms   |   Transfinite induction


(2007-01-16)   Stochastic proofs are wrong with  vanishing  probability.
Sometimes, an elusive truth is reinforced by many failures to attack it.

One celebrated example is the iterated Rabin-Miller test which tells (beyond the shadow of a doubt) whether a large number is prime or not, without actually  proving  anything when that number happens to be prime...  For a composite number, each iteration stands a substantial chance (over 75%) of proving it's not prime.  Thus, if several iterations fail to provide such a proof, we may be very confident that the number is indeed prime  (the probability of error decreases  exponentially  with the number of iterations).

Another example consists in determining whether a (large) finite group is cyclic  (knowing the factorization into primes of its order).  A finite group is cyclic if and only if it has a primitive root.  It turns out that a random element of a cyclic group is primitive with a fairly large probability  (and it can be proved to be primitive very efficently if the prime factors of the group's order are known).  Thus, if many random elements are not primitive, then the group is "almost surely" not cyclic. 


(2007-01-16)   Heuristic Arguments
Establishing the likelihood of a conjecture with an approximative proof.

For example, I argue (against the dominant opinion) that there are probably infinitely many Wieferich primes, although only two of them are known  (in spite of great efforts to find a third).

A proper heuristic argument is not a hasty generalization.  It's actually a strict mathematical proof about a modified problem, where part of the original mathematical structure is substituted with a probabilistic model.  Quantitative conclusions from such a model can be enlightening while an exact solution to the original problem remains elusive.  This may be construed as "relaxing" some mathematical constraints while retaining the problem's essential aspects.

A good heuristic argument must be supported with convincing  justifications  of the probabilistic assumptions underlaying the model.  A heuristical argument is never foolfproof (or else it would be a proper mathematical proof) but it should be nearly so...  The qualifier "heuristic" shouldn't be an excuse for sloppiness !

The accepted heuristic arguments gave the  wrong  answer for a paradoxical result which has now been proved rigorously:  Maier's theorem (1985).


(2013-05-01)   Computer Proofs
Appel & Haken used a computer to prove the 4-color theorem (1976).

They were able to reduce the general case to 1936 special cases that could not be reliably checked by hand.  The fact that a legitimate proof of a major theorem had not been verified by a human being raised eyebrows at the time.

The four-color theorem  (historical perspective)  by  John J. O'Connor  and  Edmund F. Robertson.
Kenneth Appel (1932-2013)   |   Wolfgang Haken (1928-)


(2009-06-21)   Ruling out proofs
Facts which can't be established by some or  all  types of proofs.

Generations of mathematicians have attempted to prove Euclid's fifth postulate of plane geometry from the other four axioms of Euclidean geometry.  It is now known that such a proof is not possible.  The reason why this is so is rather subtle:

If Euclidean geometry  (including the fifth postulate about parallel lines)  is at all consistent, then it can serve as a framework to describe other surfaces besides a plane.  One such surface is the sphere...

The geometry of the surface of a sphere provides one example where the first four axioms of Euclid are verified with suitable redefinitions of the concepts involved  ("points" are actually pairs of diametrically opposite locations and "lines" are great circles).  Yet, the fifth postulate is not verified, as all "lines" intersect  (there is no such thing as two "parallel" great circles).

Therefore, the fifth postulate  cannot  be a consequence of the other four.  Note that this conclusion can be reached without settling the question of whether the Euclidean postulates are consistent or not.  We just note that  if  they are consistent, then a consistent "model" can be constructed  (spherical geometry)  where the fifth one is false.  Hence, that fifth postulate is truly an independant axiom which may be assumed to be true or false.

In examples of lesser historical significance, similar arguments can be used to rule out some types of proofs for a given statement.  For example, "Fermat's last theorem" can be shown to be false within certain "models"  (involving beasts like p-adic integers).  This shows that it is a so-called  global  statement whose proof must involve some peculiar property of the rational integers besides ordinary algebra, ordering and divisibility by finitely many prime numbers.  The proof must involve something very specific to the integers, like the validity of Fermat's own infinite descent method...


(2016-01-30)   Power Tools
The worth of some general theorems is in the proofs of other theorems.

In mathematics, any proven result can be called a theorem.  However, that name is best reserved to general results which give rise to interesting proving techniques.  Here are a few examples:

  • Pigeonhole principle (Dirichlet, 1834):   If there are fewer drawers than items stored in them, there is a drawer with several items in it.
  • Fundamental theorem of arithmetic :   Factoring into primes.
  • Fubini's theorem (1907):   Switching the order of integration in a double integral  (also applicable to  absolutely  convergent series).
  • Cauchy's residue theorem.  A contour integral in the complex plane equals the sum of the residues at the singular points it encloses.
  • Stokes' theorem :   The integral of a form's derivative over some domain equals the integral of the form over that domain's border.
  • Feit-Thompson theorem (1963):   All finite groups of odd order are solvable.  This led to the full  classification theorem  (1982).

The Most Overpowered Theorems (Mathematics Stack Exchange, Nov. 2013)

border
border
visits since January 15, 2007
 (c) Copyright 2000-2016, Gerard P. Michon, Ph.D.